A Nyelvtudományi Intézet áprilisi rendezvényei

 

májusi program >>

Időpont Helyszín Előadó Előadás címe Szervező
április 1. 10.30 földszinti előadóterem Professor Ian Roberts (University of Cambridge) Types of Parametric Change

[képek]

MTA Nyelvtudományi Intézet
április 1. 14.00 földszinti előadóterem A magyar nyelv történeti mondattana, finnugor mondattani kutatások
Konzultáció a munkálatok aktuális kérdéseiről Ian Roberts
professzor, valamint a Nyelvtudományi Intézet
Finnugor Osztálya és Nyelvtörténeti Osztálya munkatársainak részvételével

MTA Nyelvtudományi Intézet

április 3. 10.30 földszinti előadóterem Professor Ian Roberts (University of Cambridge) Remarks on Head Movement

[képek]

MTA Nyelvtudományi Intézet

április 5-6. 10.00
 
földszinti előadóterem Third Budapest--Vienna Government Phonology Round Table
Szervező: Szigetvári Péter, ELTE Angol Nyelvészeti Tanszék
A szervezők minden érdeklődőt szeretettel várnak, de kérik a részvételi
szándékot előzetesen jelezni a következő címen: szigetva@nytud.hu
április 24. 10.30 ÚJ! földszinti előadóterem Edmund Gussmann (Univ. Gdansk) Polish phonology: integrating past accounts into a contemporary model MTA Nyelvtudományi Intézet
április 24. 15.00 ÚJ! földszinti előadóterem Gyuris Beáta: The Semantics of Contrastive Topics in Hungarian c. doktori (PhD) disszertációjának nyilvános védése

MEGHÍVÓ,       DISSZERTÁCIÓ,      TÉZISEK,     [képek]

MTA-ELTE Elméleti Nyelvészeti Doktori Program
április 29. 14.00 földszinti előadóterem Bakró-Nagy Marianne (MTA Nyelvtudományi Intézet) Grammatikalizálódás vagy lexikalizálódás? Diakrón Kör

 


Amennyiben az Intézet programjait e-mailben is meg szeretné kapni, kérjük küldjön egy üzenetet az Intézet e-mail címére:
linginst@nytud.hu.

További nyelvészeti programok a
Nyelvészeti portál Friss hírek rovatában olvashatók.

 

****

A Typology of Parametric Change
Ian Roberts
Downing College, University of Cambridge
 


1. Clark & Roberts (1993), Roberts (1993, 1996, 1997, 1999) and Roberts & Roussou (2000, 2003) all propose that the central mechanism of
syntactic change is the loss of movement dependencies. Arguably, this fact follows from the conservative nature of the language acquisition device, which prefers relatively simple representations over relatively more complex ones. If movement creates relatively complex representations
(essentially by introducing extra features as triggers), then we see why it is dispreferred and therefore may be diachronically lost if not robustly triggered for a given generation of first-language acquirers.

2. In current syntactic theory, the target position of all movement is a functional category. What is moved may be either lexical or functional. For illustration, let us take all movement to be of the form "L to F". It then follows that, where L-to-F movement is lost, the formerly moved material must suffer one of three fates in the new grammar: (i) it is merged in F, (ii) it is merged in L and remains there, (iii) it disappears completely. Case (i) is grammaticalisation, case (ii) is word-order change and case (iii) is loss. We can contrast cases (i) and (ii) in the obvious way as "upward" and "downward" changes. Then we can observe the following differences:

Upward changes apply just to a morphologically-defined subclass of L, recategorising it as F; these changes are local, unproductive (but sensitive to morphological subregularities), and associated with semantic and phonological "reduction".

Downward changes apply to all L, giving rise to word-order change; these changes are fully productive, and involve no semantic or phonological change to L-roots.

Examples of upward changes are the reanalysis of English modals in the 16th century, the development of Romance future/conditional forms from
Latin habere (both V becoming T), the development of negative words from minimisers (N becomes D/Q), the development of articles from
demonstratives (A becomes D), etc. Examples of downward changes are the loss of V-to-T, VSO > SVO, OV > VO (cf. Roberts (1997)) and (a case where the moved element is also functional) the loss of V2.

3. A very important aspect of this dichotomy is the fact that upward changes involve changes to interface properties (phonological and semantic
reduction), while downward changes do not. I will suggest, following the ideas sketched in Roberts & Roussou (2003, Chapter 5), that this is due to the inherent properties of functional categories. Such categories are defective at the interfaces and hence reanalysis as a functional category
involves phonological and semantic reduction. Since downward movement does not require categorial reanalysis as a functional category, no such
reduction is observed. I will also suggest that this very defectivity of functional categories underlies the preference for relatively simpler representations, understood as a ban on "extra" features, i.e. as a preference for minimal content. The central concept in this account of types of syntactic change is thus the general idea that functional categories are atomic, in that they preferentially lack structure in syntax, and obligatorily lack it at the interfaces.
 


*****

Remarks on Head Movement
Ian Roberts
Downing College, University of Cambridge
 


Chomsky (2001) argues against the inclusion of head-movement in "narrow syntax" on a number of grounds: (a) head-movement does not have the formal properties of other operations, (b) it never affects interpretation, (c) it is unclear which features trigger it, (d) it is subject to special
locality constraints, and (e) some head-movement operations are sensitive to PF notions such as second position.

I will propose a version of head-movement which does have the problem in (a), and which at the same time solves the problem in (c). I will argue
that the claims in (b), (d) and (e) are false. The result is that a kind of head movement, not exactly the same formal operation as construed hitherto, has a place in narrow syntax.